Quantum entanglement is the phenomenon of a group of particles being generated, interacting, or sharing spatial proximity in such a way that the quantum state of each particle of the group cannot be described independently of the state of the others, including when the particles are separated by a large distance. The topic of quantum entanglement is at the heart of the disparity between classical and quantum physics: entanglement is a primary feature of quantum mechanics not present in classical mechanics.[1]: 867
Measurements of physical properties such as position, momentum, spin, and polarization performed on entangled particles can, in some cases, be found to be perfectly correlated. For example, if a pair of entangled particles is generated such that their total spin is known to be zero, and one particle is found to have clockwise spin on a first axis, then the spin of the other particle, measured on the same axis, is found to be anticlockwise. However, this behavior gives rise to seemingly paradoxical effects: any measurement of a particle's properties results in an apparent and irreversible wave function collapse of that particle and changes the original quantum state. With entangled particles, such measurements affect the entangled system as a whole.
Later, however, the counterintuitive predictions of quantum mechanics were verified[6][7][8] in tests where polarization or spin of entangled particles were measured at separate locations, statistically violating Bell's inequality. In earlier tests, it could not be ruled out that the result at one point could have been subtly transmitted to the remote point, affecting the outcome at the second location.[8] However, so-called "loophole-free" Bell tests have since been performed where the locations were sufficiently separated that communications at the speed of light would have taken longer—in one case, 10,000 times longer—than the interval between the measurements.[7][6]
Albert Einstein and Niels Bohr engaged in a long-running collegial dispute about the meaning of quantum mechanics, now known as the Bohr–Einstein debates. During these debates, Einstein introduced a thought experiment about a box that emits a photon. He noted that the experimenter's choice of what measurement to make upon the box will change what can be predicted about the photon, even if the photon is very far away. This argument, which Einstein had formulated by 1931, was an early recognition of the phenomenon that would later be called entanglement.[19] That same year, Hermann Weyl observed in his textbook on group theory and quantum mechanics that quantum systems made of multiple interacting pieces exhibit a kind of Gestalt.[20][21] In 1932, Erwin Schrödinger wrote down the defining equations of quantum entnglement but set them aside, unpublished.[22] In 1935, Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen published a paper on what is now known as the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) paradox, a thought experiment that attempted to show that "the quantum-mechanical description of physical reality given by wave functions is not complete".[2] Their concept had two systems interact, then separate, and they showed that afterwards quantum mechanics cannot describe the two systems individually.
Shortly after this paper appeared, Erwin Schrödinger wrote a letter to Einstein in German in which he used the word Verschränkung (translated by himself as entanglement) "to describe the correlations between two particles that interact and then separate, as in the EPR experiment".[23] Schrödinger followed up with a full paper defining and discussing the notion of entanglement,[24] saying "I would not call [entanglement] one but rather the characteristic trait of quantum mechanics, the one that enforces its entire departure from classical lines of thought."[3]
Like Einstein, Schrödinger was dissatisfied with the concept of entanglement, because it seemed to violate the speed limit on the transmission of information implicit in the theory of relativity.[25] Einstein later referred to this as "spukhafte Fernwirkung"[26] or "spooky action at a distance".
In 1946, John Archibald Wheeler suggested studying the polarization of pairs of gamma-ray photons produced by electron–positron annihilation.[27]Chien-Shiung Wu and I. Shaknov carried out this experiment in 1949,[28] thereby demonstrating that the entangled particle pairs considered by EPR could be created in the laboratory.[29]
Despite Schrödinger's claim of its importance, little work on entanglement was published for decades after his paper was published.[24] In 1964 John S. Bell demonstrated an upper limit, seen in Bell's inequality, regarding the strength of correlations that can be produced in any theory obeying local realism, and showed that quantum theory predicts violations of this limit for certain entangled systems.[30][31]: 405 His inequality is experimentally testable, and there have been numerous relevant experiments, starting with the pioneering work of Stuart Freedman and John Clauser in 1972[32] and Alain Aspect's experiments in 1982.[33][34][35]
While Bell actively discouraged students from pursuing work like his as too esoteric, after a talk at Oxford a student named Artur Ekert suggested that these super-strong correlations could be used as a resource for communication.[36]: 315 Ekert followed up by publishing a quantum key distribution protocol called E91 that uses the violation of a Bell inequality as a proof of security.[37][1]: 874
In 1992, the entanglement concept was leveraged to propose quantum teleportation,[38] an effect that was realized experimentally in 1997.[39][40][41]
In 2022, the Nobel Prize in Physics was awarded to Aspect, Clauser, and Zeilinger "for experiments with entangled photons, establishing the violation of Bell inequalities and pioneering quantum information science".[44]
Concept
Meaning of entanglement
An entangled system can be defined to be one whose quantum state cannot be factored as a product of states of its local constituents; that is to say, they are not individual particles but are an inseparable whole. In entanglement, one constituent cannot be fully described without considering the other(s). The state of a composite system is always expressible as a sum, or superposition, of products of states of local constituents; it is entangled if this sum cannot be written as a single product term.[citation needed]
Quantum systems can become entangled through various types of interactions. For some ways in which entanglement may be achieved for experimental purposes, see the section below on methods. Entanglement is broken when the entangled particles decohere through interaction with the environment; for example, when a measurement is made.[45][46]
As an example of entanglement: a subatomic particledecays into an entangled pair of other particles. The decay events obey the various conservation laws, and as a result, the measurement outcomes of one daughter particle must be highly correlated with the measurement outcomes of the other daughter particle (so that the total momenta, angular momenta, energy, and so forth remains roughly the same before and after this process). For instance, a spin-zero particle could decay into a pair of spin-1/2 particles. Since the total spin before and after this decay must be zero (conservation of angular momentum), whenever the first particle is measured to be spin up on some axis, the other, when measured on the same axis, is always found to be spin down. (This is called the spin anti-correlated case; and if the prior probabilities for measuring each spin are equal, the pair is said to be in the singlet state.)[citation needed]
The above result may or may not be perceived as surprising. A classical system would display the same property, and a hidden variable theory would certainly be required to do so, based on conservation of angular momentum in classical and quantum mechanics alike. The difference is that a classical system has definite values for all the observables all along, while the quantum system does not. In a sense to be discussed below, the quantum system considered here seems to acquire a probability distribution for the outcome of a measurement of the spin along any axis of the other particle upon measurement of the first particle. This probability distribution is in general different from what it would be without measurement of the first particle. This may certainly be perceived as surprising in the case of spatially separated entangled particles.[citation needed]
Paradox
The paradox is that a measurement made on either of the particles apparently collapses the state of the entire entangled system—and does so instantaneously, before any information about the measurement result could have been communicated to the other particle (assuming that information cannot travel faster than light) and hence assured the "proper" outcome of the measurement of the other part of the entangled pair. In the Copenhagen interpretation, the result of a spin measurement on one of the particles is a collapse (of wave function) into a state in which each particle has a definite spin (either up or down) along the axis of measurement. The outcome is taken to be random, with each possibility having a probability of 50%. However, if both spins are measured along the same axis, they are found to be anti-correlated. This means that the random outcome of the measurement made on one particle seems to have been transmitted to the other, so that it can make the "right choice" when it too is measured.[47][unreliable source?]
The distance and timing of the measurements can be chosen so as to make the interval between the two measurements spacelike, hence, any causal effect connecting the events would have to travel faster than light. According to the principles of special relativity, it is not possible for any information to travel between two such measuring events. It is not even possible to say which of the measurements came first. For two spacelike separated events x1 and x2 there are inertial frames in which x1 is first and others in which x2 is first. Therefore, the correlation between the two measurements cannot be explained as one measurement determining the other: different observers would disagree about the role of cause and effect.
A possible resolution to the paradox is to assume that quantum theory is incomplete, and the result of measurements depends on predetermined "hidden variables".[48] The state of the particles being measured contains some hidden variables, whose values effectively determine, right from the moment of separation, what the outcomes of the spin measurements are going to be. This would mean that each particle carries all the required information with it, and nothing needs to be transmitted from one particle to the other at the time of measurement. Einstein and others (see the previous section) originally believed this was the only way out of the paradox, and the accepted quantum mechanical description (with a random measurement outcome) must be incomplete.
Violations of Bell's inequality
Local hidden variable theories fail, however, when measurements of the spin of entangled particles along different axes are considered. If a large number of pairs of such measurements are made (on a large number of pairs of entangled particles), then statistically, if the local realist or hidden variables view were correct, the results would always satisfy Bell's inequality. A number of experiments have shown in practice that Bell's inequality is not satisfied.[49][50][51] Moreover, when measurements of the entangled particles are made in moving relativistic reference frames, in which each measurement (in its own relativistic time frame) occurs before the other, the measurement results remain correlated.[52][36]: 321–324
The fundamental issue about measuring spin along different axes is that these measurements cannot have definite values at the same time―they are incompatible in the sense that these measurements' maximum simultaneous precision is constrained by the uncertainty principle. This is contrary to what is found in classical physics, where any number of properties can be measured simultaneously with arbitrary accuracy. It has been proven mathematically that compatible measurements cannot show Bell-inequality-violating correlations,[53] and thus entanglement is a fundamentally non-classical phenomenon.
Quantum teleportation and entanglement swapping
If Alice and Bob share an entangled state,[citation needed] Alice can tell Bob over a telephone call how to reproduce a quantum state she has in her lab. Alice performs a joint measurement on together with her half of the entangled state and tells Bob the results. Using Alice's results Bob operates on his half of the entangled state to make it equal to . Since Alice's original state is necessarily destroyed during the process,[citation needed] it is said to be "quantum teleported" to Bob's laboratory through this protocol.[54]: 27 [1]: 875
Entanglement swapping is an application of teleportation to make two parties that never interacted share an entangled state. We start with three parties, Alice, Bob, and Carol. Alice and Bob share an entangled state, and so do Bob and Carol, but Alice and Carol do not. Using the teleportation protocol, Bob teleports to Carol the half of the entangled state that he shares with Alice. Since teleportation preserves entanglement, this results in Alice and Carol sharing an entangled state.[citation needed]
There is a fundamental conflict, referred to as the problem of time, between the way the concept of time is used in quantum mechanics, and the role it plays in general relativity. In standard quantum theories time acts as an independent background through which states evolve, while general relativity treats time as a dynamical variable which relates directly with matter. Part of the effort to reconcile these approaches to time results in the Wheeler–DeWitt equation, which predicts the state of the universe is timeless or static, contrary to ordinary experience.[56]
Work started by Don Page and William Wootters[57][58][59] suggests that the universe appears to evolve for observers on the inside because of energy entanglement between
an evolving system and a clock system, both within the universe.[56] In this way the overall system can remain timeless while parts experience time via entanglement. The issue remains an open question closely related to attempts at theories of quantum gravity.[60][61]
Emergent gravity
In general relativity gravity arises from the curvature of spacetime and that curvature derives from the distribution of matter. However, matter is governed by quantum mechanics. Integration of these two theories faces many problems. In an (unrealistic) model space called the anti-de Sitter space, the AdS/CFT correspondence allows a quantum gravitational system to be related to a quantum field theory without gravity.[62] Using this correspondence,
Mark Van Raamsdonk suggested that spacetime arises as an emergent phenomenon of the quantum degrees of freedom that are entangled and live in the boundary of the spacetime.[63]
Non-locality and entanglement
In the media and popular science, quantum non-locality is often portrayed as being equivalent to entanglement.[citation needed] While this is true for pure bipartite quantum states, in general entanglement is only necessary for non-local correlations, but there exist mixed entangled states that do not produce such correlations.[64] One example is the Werner states that are entangled for certain values of , but can always be described using local hidden variables.[65] Moreover, it was shown that, for arbitrary numbers of particles, there exist states that are genuinely entangled but admit a local model.[66]
The mentioned proofs about the existence of local models assume that there is only one copy of the quantum state available at a time. If the particles are allowed to perform local measurements on many copies of such states, then many apparently local states (e.g., the qubit Werner states) can no longer be described by a local model. This is, in particular, true for all distillable states. However, it remains an open question whether all entangled states become non-local given sufficiently many copies.[67]
Entanglement of a state shared by two particles is necessary, but not sufficient for that state to be non-local. Entanglement is more commonly viewed as an algebraic concept, noted for being a prerequisite to non-locality as well as to quantum teleportation and to superdense coding, whereas non-locality is defined according to experimental statistics and is much more involved with the foundations and interpretations of quantum mechanics.[citation needed] In the literature "non-locality" is sometimes used to characterize concepts that differ from the non-existence of a local hidden variable model, e.g., whether states can be distinguished by local measurements and which can occur also for non-entangled states; see, e.g., [68] This non-standard use of the term[citation needed] is not discussed here.
Consider two arbitrary quantum systems A and B, with respective Hilbert spacesHA and HB. The Hilbert space of the composite system is the tensor product
If the first system is in state and the second in state , the state of the composite system is
States of the composite system that can be represented in this form are called separable states, or product states.
Not all states are separable states (and thus product states). Fix a basis for HA and a basis for HB. The most general state in HA ⊗ HB is of the form
.
This state is separable if there exist vectors so that yielding and It is inseparable if for any vectors at least for one pair of coordinates we have If a state is inseparable, it is called an 'entangled state'.
For example, given two basis vectors of HA and two basis vectors of HB, the following is an entangled state:
If the composite system is in this state, it is impossible to attribute to either system A or system B a definite pure state. Another way to say this is that while the von Neumann entropy of the whole state is zero (as it is for any pure state), the entropy of the subsystems is greater than zero. In this sense, the systems are "entangled". This has specific empirical ramifications for interferometry.[69] The above example is one of four Bell states, which are (maximally) entangled pure states (pure states of the HA ⊗ HB space, but which cannot be separated into pure states of each HA and HB).
Now suppose Alice is an observer for system A, and Bob is an observer for system B. If in the entangled state given above Alice makes a measurement in the eigenbasis of A, there are two possible outcomes, occurring with equal probability:[70][failed verification – see discussion]
Alice measures 0, and the state of the system collapses to .
Alice measures 1, and the state of the system collapses to .
If the former occurs, then any subsequent measurement performed by Bob, in the same basis, will always return 1. If the latter occurs, (Alice measures 1) then Bob's measurement will return 0 with certainty. Thus, the quantum state that describes system B has been altered by Alice performing a local measurement on system A. This remains true even if the systems A and B are spatially separated. This is the foundation of the EPR paradox.
The outcome of Alice's measurement is random. Alice cannot decide which state to collapse the composite system into, and therefore cannot transmit information to Bob by acting on her system. Causality is thus preserved, in this particular scheme. For the general argument, see no-communication theorem.
Ensembles
As mentioned above, a state of a quantum system is given by a unit vector in a Hilbert space. More generally, if one has less information about the system, then one calls it an 'ensemble' and describes it by a density matrix, which is a positive-semidefinite matrix, or a trace class when the state space is infinite-dimensional, and has trace 1. Again, by the spectral theorem, such a matrix takes the general form:
where the wi are positive-valued probabilities (they sum up to 1), the vectors αi are unit vectors, and in the infinite-dimensional case, we would take the closure of such states in the trace norm. We can interpret ρ as representing an ensemble where is the proportion of the ensemble whose states are . When a mixed state has rank 1, it therefore describes a 'pure ensemble'. When there is less than total information about the state of a quantum system we need density matrices to represent the state.
Experimentally, a mixed ensemble might be realized as follows. Consider a "black box" apparatus that spits electrons towards an observer. The electrons' Hilbert spaces are identical. The apparatus might produce electrons that are all in the same state; in this case, the electrons received by the observer are then a pure ensemble. However, the apparatus could produce electrons in different states. For example, it could produce two populations of electrons: one with state with spins aligned in the positive z direction, and the other with state with spins aligned in the negative y direction. Generally, this is a mixed ensemble, as there can be any number of populations, each corresponding to a different state.
Following the definition above, for a bipartite composite system, mixed states are just density matrices on HA ⊗ HB. That is, it has the general form
where the wi are positively valued probabilities, , and the vectors are unit vectors. This is self-adjoint and positive and has trace 1.
Extending the definition of separability from the pure case, we say that a mixed state is separable if it can be written as[71]: 131–132
where the wi are positively valued probabilities and the s and s are themselves mixed states (density operators) on the subsystems A and B respectively. In other words, a state is separable if it is a probability distribution over uncorrelated states, or product states. By writing the density matrices as sums of pure ensembles and expanding, we may assume without loss of generality that and are themselves pure ensembles. A state is then said to be entangled if it is not separable.
In general, finding out whether or not a mixed state is entangled is considered difficult. The general bipartite case has been shown to be NP-hard.[72] For the 2 × 2 and 2 × 3 cases, a necessary and sufficient criterion for separability is given by the famous Positive Partial Transpose (PPT) condition.[73]
Reduced density matrices
The idea of a reduced density matrix was introduced by Paul Dirac in 1930.[74] Consider as above systems A and B each with a Hilbert space HA, HB. Let the state of the composite system be
As indicated above, in general there is no way to associate a pure state to the component system A. However, it still is possible to associate a density matrix. Let
The sum occurs over and the identity operator in . ρA is sometimes called the reduced density matrix of ρ on subsystem A. Colloquially, we "trace out" system B to obtain the reduced density matrix on A.
For example, the reduced density matrix of A for the entangled state
discussed above is
This demonstrates that, as expected, the reduced density matrix for an entangled pure ensemble is a mixed ensemble. Also not surprisingly, the density matrix of A for the pure product state discussed above is
.
In general, a bipartite pure state ρ is entangled if and only if its reduced states are mixed rather than pure.
Two applications that use them
Reduced density matrices were explicitly calculated in different spin chains with unique ground state. An example is the one-dimensional AKLT spin chain:[75] the ground state can be divided into a block and an environment. The reduced density matrix of the block is proportional to a projector to a degenerate ground state of another Hamiltonian.
The reduced density matrix also was evaluated for XY spin chains, where it has full rank. It was proved that in the thermodynamic limit, the spectrum of the reduced density matrix of a large block of spins is an exact geometric sequence[76] in this case.
Entanglement as a resource
In quantum information theory, entangled states are considered a 'resource', i.e., something costly to produce and that allows implementing valuable transformations.[77][78] The setting in which this perspective is most evident is that of "distant labs", i.e., two quantum systems labeled "A" and "B" on each of which arbitrary quantum operations can be performed, but which do not interact with each other quantum mechanically. The only interaction allowed is the exchange of classical information, which combined with the most general local quantum operations gives rise to the class of operations called LOCC (local operations and classical communication). These operations do not allow the production of entangled states between systems A and B. But if A and B are provided with a supply of entangled states, then these, together with LOCC operations can enable a larger class of transformations. For example, an interaction between a qubit of A and a qubit of B can be realized by first teleporting A's qubit to B, then letting it interact with B's qubit (which is now a LOCC operation, since both qubits are in B's lab) and then teleporting the qubit back to A. Two maximally entangled states of two qubits are used up in this process. Thus entangled states are a resource that enables the realization of quantum interactions (or of quantum channels) in a setting where only LOCC are available, but they are consumed in the process. There are other applications where entanglement can be seen as a resource, e.g., private communication or distinguishing quantum states.[1]
Classification of entanglement
Not all quantum states are equally valuable as a resource. To quantify this value, different entanglement measures (see below) can be used, that assign a numerical value to each quantum state. However, it is often interesting to settle for a coarser way to compare quantum states. This gives rise to different classification schemes. Most entanglement classes are defined based on whether states can be converted to other states using LOCC or a subclass of these operations. The smaller the set of allowed operations, the finer the classification. Important examples are:
If two states can be transformed into each other by a local unitary operation, they are said to be in the same LU class. This is the finest of the usually considered classes. Two states in the same LU class have the same value for entanglement measures and the same value as a resource in the distant-labs setting. There is an infinite number of different LU classes (even in the simplest case of two qubits in a pure state).[79][80]
If two states can be transformed into each other by local operations including measurements with probability larger than 0, they are said to be in the same 'SLOCC class' ("stochastic LOCC"). Qualitatively, two states and in the same SLOCC class are equally powerful (since I can transform one into the other and then do whatever it allows me to do), but since the transformations and may succeed with different probability, they are no longer equally valuable. E.g., for two pure qubits there are only two SLOCC classes: the entangled states (which contains both the (maximally entangled) Bell states and weakly entangled states like ) and the separable ones (i.e., product states like ).[81][82]
Instead of considering transformations of single copies of a state (like ) one can define classes based on the possibility of multi-copy transformations. E.g., there are examples when is impossible by LOCC, but is possible. A very important (and very coarse) classification is based on the property whether it is possible to transform an arbitrarily large number of copies of a state into at least one pure entangled state. States that have this property are called distillable. These states are the most useful quantum states since, given enough of them, they can be transformed (with local operations) into any entangled state and hence allow for all possible uses. It came initially as a surprise that not all entangled states are distillable, those that are not are called 'bound entangled'.[83][1]
A different entanglement classification is based on what the quantum correlations present in a state allow A and B to do: one distinguishes three subsets of entangled states: (1) the non-local states, which produce correlations that cannot be explained by a local hidden variable model and thus violate a Bell inequality, (2) the steerable states that contain sufficient correlations for A to modify ("steer") by local measurements the conditional reduced state of B in such a way, that A can prove to B that the state they possess is indeed entangled, and finally (3) those entangled states that are neither non-local nor steerable. All three sets are non-empty.[84]
Entropy
In this section, the entropy of a mixed state is discussed as well as how it can be viewed as a measure of quantum entanglement.
Since a mixed state ρ is a probability distribution over an ensemble, this leads naturally to the definition of the von Neumann entropy:
In general, one uses the Borel functional calculus to calculate a non-polynomial function such as log2(ρ). If the nonnegative operator ρ acts on a finite-dimensional Hilbert space and has eigenvalues , log2(ρ) turns out to be nothing more than the operator with the same eigenvectors, but the eigenvalues . The Shannon entropy is then:
.
Since an event of probability 0 should not contribute to the entropy, and given that
the convention 0 log(0) = 0 is adopted. This extends to the infinite-dimensional case as well: if ρ has spectral resolution
assume the same convention when calculating
As in statistical mechanics, the more uncertainty (number of microstates) the system should possess, the larger the entropy. For example, the entropy of any pure state is zero, which is unsurprising since there is no uncertainty about a system in a pure state. The entropy of any of the two subsystems of the entangled state discussed above is log(2) (which can be shown to be the maximum entropy for 2 × 2 mixed states).
As a measure of entanglement
Entropy provides one tool that can be used to quantify entanglement, although other entanglement measures exist.[86][87] If the overall system is pure, the entropy of one subsystem can be used to measure its degree of entanglement with the other subsystems. For bipartite pure states, the von Neumann entropy of reduced states is the unique measure of entanglement in the sense that it is the only function on the family of states that satisfies certain axioms required of an entanglement measure.[88]
It is a classical result that the Shannon entropy achieves its maximum at, and only at, the uniform probability distribution {1/n, ..., 1/n}. Therefore, a bipartite pure state ρ ∈ HA ⊗ HB is said to be a maximally entangled state if the reduced state of each subsystem of ρ is the diagonal matrix
For mixed states, the reduced von Neumann entropy is not the only reasonable entanglement measure.
As an aside, the information-theoretic definition is closely related to entropy in the sense of statistical mechanics[89] (comparing the two definitions in the present context, it is customary to set the Boltzmann constantk = 1). For example, by properties of the Borel functional calculus, we see that for any unitary operatorU,
Indeed, without this property, the von Neumann entropy would not be well-defined.
In particular, U could be the time evolution operator of the system, i.e.,
where H is the Hamiltonian of the system. Here the entropy is unchanged.
Entanglement measures quantify the amount of entanglement in a (often viewed as a bipartite) quantum state. As aforementioned, entanglement entropy is the standard measure of entanglement for pure states (but no longer a measure of entanglement for mixed states). For mixed states, there are some entanglement measures in the literature[86] and no single one is standard.
Most (but not all) of these entanglement measures reduce for pure states to entanglement entropy, and are difficult (NP-hard) to compute for mixed states as the dimension of the entangled system grows.[91]
Entanglement has many applications in quantum information theory. With the aid of entanglement, otherwise impossible tasks may be achieved.
Among the best-known applications of entanglement are superdense coding and quantum teleportation.[92]
Most researchers believe that entanglement is necessary to realize quantum computing (although this is disputed by some).[93]
Entanglement is used in some protocols of quantum cryptography,[94][95] but to prove the security of quantum key distribution (QKD) under standard assumptions does not require entanglement.[96] However, the device independent security of QKD is shown exploiting entanglement between the communication partners.[97]
In August 2014, Brazilian researcher Gabriela Barreto Lemos, from the University of Vienna, and team were able to "take pictures" of objects using photons that had not interacted with the subjects, but were entangled with photons that did interact with such objects.[98] The idea has been adapted to make infrared images using only standard cameras that are insensitive to infrared.[99]
Entangled states
There are several canonical entangled states that appear often in theory and experiments.
which reduces to the Bell state for M = 2. The traditional GHZ state was defined for M = 3. GHZ states are occasionally extended to qudits, i.e., systems of d rather than 2 dimensions.
Also for M > 2 qubits, there are spin squeezed states, a class of squeezed coherent states satisfying certain restrictions on the uncertainty of spin measurements, which are necessarily entangled.[100] Spin squeezed states are good candidates for enhancing precision measurements using quantum entanglement.[101]
This is like the Bell state except the basis kets 0 and 1 have been replaced with "the N photons are in one mode" and "the N photons are in the other mode".
Finally, there also exist twin Fock states for bosonic modes, which can be created by feeding a Fock state into two arms leading to a beam splitter. They are the sum of multiple of NOON states, and can be used to achieve the Heisenberg limit.[102]
For the appropriately chosen measures of entanglement, Bell, GHZ, and NOON states are maximally entangled while spin squeezed and twin Fock states are only partially entangled. The partially entangled states are generally easier to prepare experimentally.
It is also possible to create entanglement between quantum systems that never directly interacted, through the use of entanglement swapping. Two independently prepared, identical particles may also be entangled if their wave functions merely spatially overlap, at least partially.[107]
Testing a system for entanglement
A density matrix ρ is called separable if it can be written as a convex sum of product states, namely
with probabilities. By definition, a state is entangled if it is not separable.
For 2-qubit and qubit-qutrit systems (2 × 2 and 2 × 3 respectively) the simple Peres–Horodecki criterion provides both a necessary and a sufficient criterion for separability, and thus—inadvertently—for detecting entanglement. However, for the general case, the criterion is merely a necessary one for separability, as the problem becomes NP-hard when generalized.[108][109] Other separability criteria include (but not limited to) the range criterion, reduction criterion, and those based on uncertainty relations.[110][111][112][113] See Ref.[114] for a review of separability criteria in discrete-variable systems and Ref.[115] for a review on techniques and challenges in experimental entanglement certification in discrete-variable systems.
A numerical approach to the problem is suggested by Jon Magne Leinaas, Jan Myrheim and Eirik Ovrum in their paper "Geometrical aspects of entanglement".[116] Leinaas et al. offer a numerical approach, iteratively refining an estimated separable state towards the target state to be tested, and checking if the target state can indeed be reached. An implementation of the algorithm (including a built-in Peres–Horodecki criterion testing) is "StateSeparator" web-app.
In continuous variable systems, the Peres–Horodecki criterion also applies. Specifically, Simon[117] formulated a particular version of the Peres–Horodecki criterion in terms of the second-order moments of canonical operators and showed that it is necessary and sufficient for -mode Gaussian states (see Ref.[118] for a seemingly different but essentially equivalent approach). It was later found[119] that Simon's condition is also necessary and sufficient for -mode Gaussian states, but no longer sufficient for -mode Gaussian states. Simon's condition can be generalized by taking into account the higher order moments of canonical operators[120][121] or by using entropic measures.[122][123]
On August 16, 2016, the world's first quantum communications satellite was launched from the Jiuquan Satellite Launch Center in China, the Quantum Experiments at Space Scale (QUESS) mission, nicknamed "Micius" after the ancient Chinese philosopher. The satellite was intended to demonstrate the feasibility of quantum communication between Earth and space, and test quantum entanglement over unprecedented distances.[124]
In the 16 June 2017, issue of Science, Yin et al. report setting a new quantum entanglement distance record of 1,203 km, demonstrating the survival of a two-photon pair and a violation of a Bell inequality, reaching a CHSH valuation of 2.37±0.09, under strict Einstein locality conditions, from the Micius satellite to bases in Lijian, Yunnan and Delingha, Quinhai, increasing the efficiency of transmission over prior fiberoptic experiments by an order of magnitude.[125][126]
Entanglement of top quarks
In 2023 the LHC using techniques from quantum tomography measured entanglement at the highest energy so far,[127][128][129] a rare intersection between quantum information and high energy physics based on theoretical work first proposed in 2021.[130] The experiment was carried by the ATLAS detector measuring the spin of top-quark pair production and the effect was observed witha more than 5σ level of significance, the top quark is the heaviest known particle and therefore has a very short lifetime ( ≈ 10−25 s) being the only quark that decays before undergoing hadronization (~ 10−23 s) and spin decorrelation (~ 10−21 s), so the spin information is transferred without much loss to the leptonic decays products that will be caught by the detector.[131] The spin polarization and correlation of the particles was measured and tested for entanglement with concurrence as well as the Peres–Horodecki criterion and subsequently the effect has been confirmed too in the CMS detector.[132][133]
Living organisms (green sulphur bacteria) have been studied as mediators to create quantum entanglement between otherwise non-interacting light modes, showing high entanglement between light and bacterial modes, and to some extent, even entanglement within the bacteria.[141]
^Physicist John Bell depicts the Einstein camp in this debate in his article entitled "Bertlmann's socks and the nature of reality", p. 143 of Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics: "For EPR that would be an unthinkable 'spooky action at a distance'. To avoid such action at a distance they have to attribute, to the space-time regions in question, real properties in advance of observation, correlated properties, which predetermine the outcomes of these particular observations. Since these real properties, fixed in advance of observation, are not contained in quantum formalism, that formalism for EPR is incomplete. It may be correct, as far as it goes, but the usual quantum formalism cannot be the whole story." And again on p. 144 Bell says: "Einstein had no difficulty accepting that affairs in different places could be correlated. What he could not accept was that an intervention at one place could influence, immediately, affairs at the other." Downloaded 5 July 2011 from Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics(PDF). CERN. ISBN0521334950. Archived from the original(PDF) on 12 April 2015. Retrieved 14 June 2014.
^Heathcote, Adrian (2021). "Multiplicity and indiscernability". Synthese. 198 (9): 8779–8808. doi:10.1007/s11229-020-02600-8. For Weyl clearly anticipated entanglement by noting that the pure state of a coupled system need not be determined by the states of the composites [...] Weyl deserves far more credit than he has received for laying out the basis for entanglement—more than six years before Schrödinger coined the term.
^Christandl, Matthias (2006). The Structure of Bipartite Quantum States – Insights from Group Theory and Cryptography (PhD thesis). University of Cambridge. pp. vi, iv. arXiv:quant-ph/0604183. Bibcode:2006PhDT.......289C.
^Alisa Bokulich, Gregg Jaeger, Philosophy of Quantum Information and Entanglement, Cambridge University Press, 2010, p. xv.
^Letter from Einstein to Max Born, 3 March 1947; The Born-Einstein Letters; Correspondence between Albert Einstein and Max and Hedwig Born from 1916 to 1955, Walker, New York, 1971. Cited in Hobson, M. P.; et al. (1998). "Quantum Entanglement and Communication Complexity". SIAM J. Comput. 30 (6): 1829–1841. CiteSeerX10.1.1.20.8324.)
^ abcGilder, Louisa (2009). The age of entanglement: when quantum physics was reborn (1. Vintage Book ed.). New York, NY: Vintage Books. ISBN978-1-4000-9526-1.
^Del Santo, F; Schwarzhans, E. (2022). ""Philosophysics" at the University of Vienna: The (Pre-) History of Foundations of Quantum Physics in the Viennese Cultural Context". Physics in Perspective. 24 (2–3): 125–153. arXiv:2011.11969. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198844495.013.0026 (inactive 21 November 2024).{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of November 2024 (link)
^Dehlinger, Dietrich; Mitchell, M. W. (2002). "Entangled photons, nonlocality, and Bell inequalities in the undergraduate laboratory". American Journal of Physics. 70 (9): 903–910. arXiv:quant-ph/0205171. doi:10.1119/1.1498860.
^Nielsen, Michael A.; Chuang, Isaac L. (2010). Quantum computation and quantum information (10 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN978-0-521-63503-5.
^Franchini, F.; Its, A. R.; Korepin, V. E.; Takhtajan, L. A. (2010). "Spectrum of the density matrix of a large block of spins of the XY model in one dimension". Quantum Information Processing. 10 (3): 325–341. arXiv:1002.2931. doi:10.1007/s11128-010-0197-7. S2CID6683370.
^Pirandola, S.; U. L. Andersen; L. Banchi; M. Berta; D. Bunandar; R. Colbeck; D. Englund; T. Gehring; C. Lupo; C. Ottaviani; J. L. Pereira; M. Razavi; J. Shamsul Shaari; M. Tomamichel; V. C. Usenko; G. Vallone; P. Villoresi; P. Wallden (2020). "Advances in quantum cryptography". Adv. Opt. Photon. 12 (4): 1012–1236. arXiv:1906.01645. Bibcode:2020AdOP...12.1012P. doi:10.1364/AOP.361502. S2CID174799187.
^
Shadbolt, P. J.; Verde, M. R.; Peruzzo, A.; Politi, A.; Laing, A.; Lobino, M.; Matthews, J. C. F.; Thompson, M. G.; O'Brien, J. L. (2012). "Generating, manipulating and measuring entanglement and mixture with a reconfigurable photonic circuit". Nature Photonics. 6 (1): 45–59. arXiv:1108.3309. Bibcode:2012NaPho...6...45S. doi:10.1038/nphoton.2011.283. S2CID56206588.
^Gurvits, L., Classical deterministic complexity of Edmonds' problem and quantum entanglement, in Proceedings of the 35th ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing, ACM Press, New York, 2003.
^CMS Collaboration (6 June 2024). "Observation of quantum entanglement in top quark pair production in proton–proton collisions at √s = 13 TeV". Reports on Progress in Physics. 87 (11). arXiv:2406.03976. doi:10.1088/1361-6633/ad7e4d. PMID39315475.
^CMS Collaboration (17 September 2024). "Measurements of polarization and spin correlation and observation of entanglement in top quark pairs using lepton+jets events from proton-proton collisions at $\sqrt{s}$ = 13 TeV". arXiv:2409.11067 [hep-ex].
Bengtsson, I.; Życzkowski, K. (2006). Geometry of Quantum States: An Introduction to Quantum Entanglement. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. second, revised edition (2017)